General
Assume a complex proposition of the form ‘S↴
, although ↴S
’. ↴S
is the concessive proposition. All such complex propositions share the following properties:
- A conditional ‘if
↴S
, notS↴
’ (q → ¬p
) is presupposed. ↴S
is taken for granted.S↴
is asserted.
The presupposition #1 is normally grounded in a causal relation between S↴
and ↴S
. Consider, for instance, a concessive construction such as .
. | Although I exerted myself, I flunked the exam. |
Such a sentence involves the presupposition ‘if I exert myself, I should pass the exam,’ which it contradicts. The presupposition is understood to be based on a causal relation between exerting oneself and passing exams. In this respect, concessive constructions are semantically based on causal constructions. By the combination of conditions #2 and #3, the speaker denies the conditional (thus trying to cancel it from the universe of discourse).
Subtypes of concessive relations are generated by the following alternatives:
- As for the above condition #2, the proposition
↴S
of the subordinate clause may either be factive or be assumed hypothetically. - As for the above condition #1, the conditional relation between
S↴
and↴S
may hinge on some degree to which↴S
is the case.
Accordingly, the following subsections are devoted to factive vs. conditional concessives and to indifferent concessives.
Conditional and factive concessives
In a conditional concessive (), the subordinate proposition (↴S
) is explicitly assumed rather than presupposed. is an example.
. | Even if I exert myself, I will flunk the exam. |
The conditional concessive combines two independent features:
- It explicitly assumes the protasis
↴S
. It is, consequently, a conditional. - It presupposes the implication
q → ¬p
and contradicts it. It is, consequently, a concessive.
For this reason, the construction is called both conditional concessive and concessive conditional in the literature and in the present script. The concessive conditional is also treated as a subtype of the conditional.
In a factive concessive (), the speaker takes the reality of ↴S
for granted. ↴S
seems to be asserted rather than presupposed.1 The clause representing ↴S
thus defined is a (factive) concessive clause. In English, most factive concessive clauses are introduced by (al)though.2
Just as the conditional concessive bears the said paradigmatic relation to a conditional, contradicting it, so a factive concessive bears a paradigmatic, viz. a contradictory, relation to a causal clause: It presupposes the relation '↴S
causes ¬p
' and contradicts it. Thus, presupposes the causal relation ‘because I exerted myself, I did not flunk the exam’ and contradicts it.
Indifferent concessives
In a variety of the concessive relation, ↴S
involves variation on some parameter and the presupposed conditional concerns a certain value on this parameter which would prevent the realization of S↴
. Such an indifferent concessive relation may be coded by an indifferent (relative) clause of the kind of .
. | However much I exerted myself, I always flunked the exams. |
The two binary subdivisions of concessive relations are logically independent and cross-classify. is an indifferent conditional concessive.
. | However much I may exert myself, I will flunk the exams. |
1 The negation test on presupposition status is not easily applied to a sentence such as .
2 The English conjunction although nicely illustrates the necessity of distinguishing between the onomasiological and the semasiological approach: All factive concessive clauses may be introduced by although; but not every clause introduced by although is a factive concessive clause. In the sentence “Dowty ... proposes ... a different decomposition system from the one presented here, although this system has many features in common with Dowty's proposal.” (Van Valin & La Polla 1997:655), no concessive relation between the two propositions is involved, since the second proposition is not meant to be an obstacle to the first one. This use of although appears to involve a kind of corrective contrast.